An open access publication of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences
Spring 2006

American philosophy in the twentieth century

Authors
Dagfinn Kaare Follesdal and Michael Friedman

Dagfinn Føllesdal, a Fellow of the American Academy since 1984, is Clarence Irving Lewis Professor of Philosophy at Stanford University. He has written five books, including “Rational Argumentation” (1986) and “Referential Opacity and Modal Logic” (2004). He is also coeditor of “Phenomenology and the Formal Sciences” (with Thomas M. Seebohm and Jitendra Nath Mohanty, 1991) and editor of the series “The Philosophy of W. V. Quine” (2000).

Michael Friedman, a Fellow of the American Academy since 1997, is Frederick P. Rehmus Family Professor of Humanities at Stanford University. His research interests include Kant and the history of twentieth-century philosophy, in particular, the interaction between philosophy and the exact sciences from Kant through the logical empiricists. Among his publications are “Kant and the Exact Sciences” (1992), “Reconsidering Logical Positivism” (1999), “A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger” (2000), and “Dynamics of Reason” (2001).

In 1900, Europe was the philosophical center of the world, as it was the center for science and scholarship in all fields. America was a province–in philosophy there were few teachers and few students. It was to Europe one went for advanced study of philosophy, and some of the main American philosophers, such as William James, eagerly did so. However, some influence had begun to flow in the opposite direction as well. James’s Principles of Psychology (1890) was widely studied in Europe and was a major influence on the young Edmund Husserl when he started to develop phenomenology. Charles Sanders Peirce’s logical work also became well-known in Europe, primarily because of the attention Ernst Schroeder gave it in his important Vorlesungen ueber die Algebra der Logik (1890–1905).

Now, one hundred years later, the situation has changed dramatically. America has more philosophers and more philosophy students than do all the countries in Europe combined. But mere numbers are no good indication of quality. Two better indicators are where students go and where one prefers to publish. Students from Europe and the rest of the world now go to America to do their graduate work. The American Ph.D. programs are known to give a broad and thorough education in philosophy, with great stress on written work. Unlike their European counterparts, American students hand in written work several times a term and receive detailed comments from their teachers. European universities are too understaffed to give similar attention and feedback to their students, and they often lack teaching staff in subfields that in America are required for accreditation. Not only in philosophy, but in all disciplines, the American system of graduate education is one of the main factors in explaining America’s increasing dominance in science and scholarship.

That students go to America to study philosophy, however, may attest more to the quality of American higher education than to the quality of American philosophy. Another indicator of quality, though, is that one has to read English in order to have access to the best scholarly contributions and write English in order to be read by the best scholars. English has taken over as the main language of scholarship, in philosophy as in other fields. That English has replaced German and French as the primary language of science and scholarship reflects, it seems, a corresponding move of most of the research activity.

What happened in the twentieth century that transformed America from a province to a center for philosophy?

.  .  .

To read this essay or subscribe to Dædalus, visit the Dædalus access page
Access now